"The higher American patriotism, on the other hand, combines loyalty to historical tradition and precedent with the imaginative projection of an ideal national Promise."
- Herbert Croly
Herbert Croly is not exactly a household name, but he should be.
Seven decades after his death, we are still living in the political
world his ideas built--and struggling to escape it.
Croly did two very important things: He wrote
The Promise of American Life, published in 1909, which
crystallized the thought of the Progressive movement as it assumed
significant, multiparty political influence. And, five years later,
he founded The New Republic, which gave--and gives--voice
to those ideas.
Croly's central message was that the government's job is to
solve social problems and to actively shape the future, not to be a
neutral referee. "To conceive of a better American future as a
consummation which will take care of itself,--as the necessary
result of our customary conditions, institutions, and
ideas,--persistence in such a conception is admirably designed to
deprive American life of any promise at all," he wrote. Croly's
ideas influenced, among other contemporaries, Theodore Roosevelt
and Woodrow Wilson, political rivals who in retrospect had more
fundamental agreements than differences.
Crolyism overturned the ideal of limited government in favor of
a combination of elite power--commissions to regulate and plan--and
mass democracy. It was this pragmatic progressivism, not socialist
utopianism, that extinguished classical liberalism as the general
philosophy of American government. Frustrated with constitutional
limits, Croly wrote, "The security of private property and personal
liberty, and a proper distribution of activity between the local
and the central governments, demanded [at the time of the
Constitution's framing], and within limits still demand, adequate
legal guarantees. It remains none the less true, however, that
every popular government should in the end, and after a necessarily
prolonged deliberation, possess the power of taking any action,
which, in the opinion of a decisive majority of the people, is
demanded by the public welfare." This statement, while extreme,
pretty much sums up today's governing philosophy.
In Crolyism, we find the assumptions that underlie just about
every current political debate: Government is supposed to pick
sides and solve problems. The only questions are which sides and
how. When that most conventional of Washington columnists, Morton
Kondracke, writes that "the solution [for Republicans] lies in the
same place that Clinton found victory in 1996: centrist
problem-solving," he is affirming the Crolyist creed.
So, far more explicitly, are Weekly Standard editors
William Kristol and David Brooks when they declare in The Wall
Street Journal, "Wishing to be left alone isn't a governing
doctrine....What is missing from today's conservatism is the appeal
to American greatness." By their own admission, Kristol and Brooks
have only the haziest of agendas: "It would be silly to try to lay
out some sort of 10-point program for American greatness." They
simply know what they want to quash--the idea that American
greatness is emergent, rather than planned, and that it does not
emerge from Washington. "American purpose," writes Brooks, "can
find its voice only in Washington."
"As long as Americans believed they were able to fulfill a noble
national Promise merely by virtue of maintaining intact a set of
political institutions and by the vigorous individual pursuit of
private ends, their allegiances to their national fulfillment
remained more a matter of words than of deeds," wrote Croly. Echoes
Brooks in the Standard, "If they think of nothing but
their narrow self-interest, of their commercial activities,
[Americans] lose a sense of grand aspiration and noble purpose."
Like Croly, Brooks wants to crush the idea that government's job is
simply to maintain free institutions and to let Americans, as
individuals and in association, do the rest.
As Jim Glassman and I have written elsewhere, such conservatives
have trouble finding American greatness because they are deeply
alienated from the textures of American life--from the private
activities in which Americans express grand aspirations and noble
purpose. (See "'National
Greatness' or Conservative Malaise?," The Wall Street
Journal, September 25.) They view America as a rotten society,
whose very creativity and exuberance is a cause for dismay.
But Kristol and Brooks are on to something: We do need to talk
about governing doctrines. For the first time since Croly's era, we
are at an inflection point in American politics, a time when the
fundamental definition of what politics is all about could change.
This redefinition is not a matter of party realignment but of big
ideas. America's Crolyist assumptions are no longer secure.
Like the change in Croly's time, this inflection point is a
product of intellectual and political trends over several decades.
Belief in the practical power of technocracy has steadily declined,
among both elites and the general public, since the mid-1960s. The
old habit of "got a problem, get a program" remains, but enthusiasm
for those new programs died in a gas line sometime during the
Carter administration. From urban renewal in the late '50s to the
S&L bailouts of the 1980s, Crolyism has not delivered on its
grand promises.
As government has grown and special interests have multiplied,
bureaucracies that once seemed to function reasonably well have
become decadent, rigid, and insulated: Until the late 1950s, muses
Nathan Glazer in The New Republic, the New York City
public schools did a good job. What happened? Glazer tepidly blames
the '60s, missing dynamics that political scientists find just
about everywhere. It's hard to explain the high-handed incompetence
of the U.S. Postal Service--and the contrasting competence of FedEx
and UPS--by invoking the counterculture. NASA's sluggishness has
nothing to do with hippies.
As the recent Senate hearings on the IRS revealed, picking sides
and solving problems also means treating Americans not as equal
citizens but as unequal subjects. A Crolyist government has a
natural but nasty tendency to abuse its citizens. Its governing
doctrine has a touch of the dominatrix. "The Promise of American
life," wrote Croly, "is to be fulfilled--not merely by a maximum
amount of economic freedom, but by a certain measure of discipline;
not merely by the abundant satisfaction of individual desires, but
by a large measure of individual subordination and
self-denial."
After 70 years of increasing subordination, it's no wonder
"leave us alone" is a slogan appealing enough to unite, on
occasion, an unruly coalition of libertarians and social
conservatives. As long as Crolyism is still generating new
schemes--Internet censorship, HMO regulation, smoking bans,
manipulative tax credits, endless databases and ID cards, mandatory
"voluntary" TV ratings, etc., etc., etc.--simply saying no
is a serious, and necessary, political position. (The failure of
the Republican "leave us alone" coalition is evident in these
examples, since social conservatives ardently support about half
these laws.)
As slogans go, "leave us alone" is not bad: It suggests that
there is something precious and vital in private pursuits,
something that is threatened by a government bent on subordination.
Not so good is "government doesn't work," which, along with
variations on the same theme, is popular in libertarian circles. At
the very moment when Crolyism is vulnerable, such anti-government
sloganeering accepts and reinforces a Crolyist definition of
"government" as synonymous with the unlimited administrative state.
It thereby jettisons the entire classical liberal tradition--which
is very much supportive of "government" properly constrained--in
favor of a vague anarchism. As an alternative to Crolyist
subordination, "government doesn't work" offers the Hobbesian state
of nature. That is exactly what Croly's many heirs, on both the
right and the left, want people to see as the choice.
Crolyism was not built on slogans, and it cannot be displaced by
them. A new governing doctrine, like the old one, requires two
components: an inspiring vision of private life and a sophisticated
vision of government. Fortunately, both of these visions exist. The
challenge is to develop and communicate them.
America is an amazing place: creative, generous, and productive,
with so many cultural nooks and crannies that no one can comprehend
them all. Ours is a country whose greatness lies in its plenitude,
the sheer diversity of niches--business, cultural, artistic,
stylistic, intellectual, athletic, philanthropic, technical, you
name it--it continuously creates and fills. (I owe the apt term
plenitude to anthropologist Grant McCracken's book by that
name, available at www.cultureby.com.) Plenitude is
exciting, fun, stimulating, cool. It allows more people to be happy
more of the time. It defies rigid status categories, whether
"traditional" or "multicultural," in favor of the fluidity of
choice and contract. It is a source of progress and competition, of
the essential variations in the evolution of a dynamic
civilization.
Crolyism despises plenitude. As a governing doctrine, it is
inherently intolerant, demanding conformity to a central purpose.
"In becoming responsible for the subordination of the individual to
the demand of a dominant and constructive national purpose," wrote
Croly, "the American state will in effect be making itself
responsible for a morally and socially desirable distribution of
wealth." To the distribution of wealth, we can add a host of other
private matters, from the correct relation between employers and
employees to the intimate structures of family life to the proper
forms of art. In a Crolyist state, the National Organization for
Women can imagine no way to peacefully coexist with the Promise
Keepers--for one vision or the other must define the "dominant and
constructive national purpose."
Classical liberalism, by contrast, was built on the idea of
peaceful coexistence. It evolved as an alternative to unceasing
religious wars. Its 21st-century version--which emphasizes
dispersed knowledge, competition and feedback, and evolutionary
learning, as well as personal freedom--is the only political
philosophy that makes room for plenitude. "There is a
common culture that unites the world of plenitude," McCracken
writes coyly. "It is, I think, and this will please no one, the
marketplace. This is the great lingua franca of the contemporary
world. As long as we can meet somewhere in the exchange of
something for the benefit of someone, we have a foundation that can
sustain plenitude."
The question, then, is how to sustain in turn the foundations of
the marketplace--such free institutions as property rights,
contract, the rule of law, and freedom of conscience and
expression. This is not an easy question, which is why it is so
often finessed with slogans. It actually has several components:
how to move toward freer institutions, how to protect them, and how
to define them. What exactly is meant by "property rights" or "the
rule of law" is not obvious in every context--What about commons?
Spillover effects? Intellectual property? Incomplete
contracts?--nor is the relation between legal institutions and
cultural habits and beliefs.
By dismissing free institutions as annoying impediments to
political action, Crolyism has pushed such fundamental issues out
of public view. But scholars have continued to think about them. As
a serious intellectual movement, classical liberalism is not only
as vibrant as ever, it has become downright trendy. The questions
it asks are interesting, deep, and practical, a sure recipe for
scholarly attention.
In mid-September, a remarkable conference was held at Washington
University in St. Louis, the first meeting of the International
Society for the New Institutional Economics. NIE builds on the work
of two Nobel laureates, Ronald Coase, who has asked such basic
questions as, "Why are there firms?," and Douglass North, who asks
why some economies have grown faster than others and examines how
they developed the institutions that permitted that growth. With no
advertising except the society's Web site
(sykuta.business.pitt.edu/NIE), the conference organizers expected
40 or 50 attendees; they had to close registration at more than
200, from 20 countries and all the social sciences.
The NIE conference was testimony not only to the power of
cyberspace to nurture international communities but also to the
vitality of serious alternatives to Crolyism (even at the World
Bank, where NIE-inspired researchers are actually pondering such
issues as "the sources of secure property and contractual rights").
Conventional political discourse continues to define
government as the manipulative determiner of national
purpose, but the twin challenges of Third World development and
postcommunist transition have revived the fundamental insight of
classical liberalism--the idea that government best serves its
citizens by limiting itself to enforcing neutral rules. Figuring
out how to turn that insight into policy is both an intellectual
and a political challenge. But the idea itself is a "governing
doctrine" worthy of American greatness.
No comments:
Post a Comment